September 10 2014, 4.28pm EDT
Moralityand our lives with animals
AUTHOR
Our relationship with
non-human animals must be understood as a question of morality. Patrick Bouquet/Flickr
The
traditional point of view in western intellectual thought – and one which is
reflected in our own day-to–day views – is that of human exceptionalism,
or anthropocentrism: the belief that humans are the central and most important
beings on the planet.
We
see this belief time and again throughout our intellectual heritage. From early
thinkers such as Protagoras, who argued “man is the measure
of all things”, through to contemporary expressions of the “heart-breaking
specialness” of the human, anthropocentric views abound and are largely
uncontested.
That
we take them for granted is their power. The hierarchical thinking that places
humans above animals can be traced back to our intellectual roots in Ancient
Greece (at least in so far as the West is concerned) and in the Judeo-Christian
tradition.
The
more influential paradigm to emerge from ancient Greece found itself manifest
in the thoughts of Aristotle (384BC–322BC). He argued that nature consisted of
a hierarchy with “man” at the top of this Scala Natura.
Those with the least reasoning ability existed for the sake of those with the
most in order to ensure survival; so plants exist for the sake of animals,
animals for the sake of humans, and so on.
The
endurance of this belief held the door wide open for the likes of Rene Descartes (1596-1650) and his construction of
non-human animals as behaviouristic machines. The idea that animals are “other”
to humans, that they do not share any of our fundamental cognitive abilities
and that they merely react to stimuli outside them through habit, like
machines, are all direct consequences of this line of thought.
In
turn this led to the argument that considerations of animal mentation and
consciousness were irrelevant, and following the Aristotelian line of thought
we, as superior beings, have the right to do with inferior beings whatever we
choose.
Descartes'
denial of the existence of animal consciousness set the tone for debates about
the moral status of animals and animal rights. Whether animals are conscious
has remained the central issue when we discuss whether animals deserve rights
or not.
As
critics have pointed out, though, this debate often tells us more about how we
perceive humans. It underlines our belief in human exceptionalism. Tied
irrevocably to our beliefs in our own civility, versus the barbarity of nature,
this view sets us apart from and above other life on the planet.
We
believe ourselves to have certain unique traits (the capacity for language or
culture, say) that distinguish us from other species. Part and parcel of this
belief is the view that we can control nature and therefore have a right to use
it to meet our own needs. This often includes other animals. And so
anthropocentric viewpoints legitimate such practices as meat eating, factory
farming, the uses of animals for entertainment and clothing and so on.
Most
attempts from moral philosophy to challenge this weighty intellectual tradition
are mired in their own anthropocentric worldview. Key figures such as Peter Singer,
the author of the “bible of the animal rights movement” (Animal
Liberation, 1975), Ryder (Victims
of Science, 1975) and Midgley (Animals and Why
They Matter, 1984) become bogged down in attempts to prove that
animals have enough similarity to humans to warrant their inclusion in our
moral frameworks.
This
relegates animals to an inferior status by implication: unless they are similar
enough to us in their abilities they do not deserve equal moral worth.
Throughout
history there have been those who contested this view.
From
the 1970s onwards there has been an animal “liberation” movement which aims to
secure rights for nonhuman animals.
More
recently, though, the location of this ideology – in liberal humanism – has
been questioned: should we be aiming to secure rights for nonhuman animals
based on their similarity to us, or should aim to understand and respect their
differences along with their right to live on this planet alongside us?
The
result is a re-thinking, or re-framing, of human-animal relations as we move to
recognise the intrinsic value of other creatures with whom we share this
planet.
Traditional views are
slowly being eroded and with this comes a certain freedom. Biologists are
finding themselves able to legitimately investigate topics such as the
emotional and moral lives of animals without being summarily dismissed for their
erroneous anthropomorphism. From the Greek anthropos andmorphe meaning human and form respectively,
this is the attribution of human characteristics to nonhuman “objects” which
includes other animals.
From
17th century philosophic objections from the likes of Francis Bacon and Baruch
Spinoza, and finally finding its pinnacle of expression in the radical
behaviourism of the mid-20th century, anthropomorphism has come to be
synonymous with un-scientific practices. It attributes emotions and mental
states to animals that cannot be proven by scientific standards. (Note that the
lack of emotions and perceived impoverished mental lives of nonhuman animals
was and still is used to justify their ill treatment and inferior moral
status.)
Even
so anthropomorphism remains a consistent and persistent part of human practices
with other animals. (Do you talk to your dog and believe s/he is guilty when
found destroying the contents of the rubbish bin? You are not alone.)
Anthropomorphism
is also a deeply ingrained part of modern human cultures and can be seen in
folklore and cultural representations (think Skippy or Lassie, among others).
In this way anthropomorphism is one of the ways in which we disrupt previously
assumed clear delineations between human and nonhuman, between human and
animal.
And
by doing so, at a practical level we call into question the superiority of
humans. Anthropomorphic practices allow nonhuman animals agency and in turn
move them from being perceived as object to subject.
Not
only does this blur the carefully erected and maintained boundaries between
humans and other animals, but it leads to tricky questions: if animals do feel
in similar ways to humans then how do we justify current (ab)uses of them?
The
age-old justifications based on difference – that they do not feel pain and so
on – no longer apply and we find ourselves with a set of social practices such
as eating meat, the morality of which is no longer clear-cut.
Nenhum comentário:
Postar um comentário